Wednesday, 11 November 2015

TERM PAPER ON IMMANUEL KANT



TERM PAPER

CRITIQUE OF JUDGEMENT- IMMANUEL KANT



MITHYA A
I MA ECL
LCL05151


Immanuel Kant and Critique of Judgment

All our knowledge begins with the senses, proceeds then to the understanding, and ends with reason. There is nothing higher than reason; this is the comment of Immanuel Kant- a major enlightenment philosopher. Kant’s this observation contributes to the philosophies of later periods, up to modern times. Immanuel Kant is noted for his contribution in the field of Aestheticism, Enlightenment etc.  Kant and Hegel often mentioned jointly for their contribution to the field of modern philosophy. Both Kant and Hegel were spokesmen of ‘art for art’s sake’ and the ‘art ends in themselves.
Immanuel Kant born in East Prussia in the year 1724, he attended university education from there and became professor at that same university. He died in the year 1804; he was never travelled outside Prussia and never married. The biographical details give the information that Kant is secluded to his country and he was not a social being. But his knowledge travelled beyond the boundaries and he was actually inspired by the aesthetic ideas of Edmund Alaxander Baugarten, David Hume and Edmund Burke. Immanuel Kant’s major works include Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime, Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of Practical Reason, and Critique of Judgment. His Critique of Judgment is considered as equal to Aristotle’s Poetics both are contributes to treatise on art. Like Aristotle, Kant also gives importance to spectators’ response rather than artistic production.
                   Kant’s major works begin with the Critique of Pure Reason in which he develops his critical philosophy to overcome David Hume’s ‘Subjectivist Skepticism’. Kant wished to define the boundaries of human reason and endeavor in his first book. The first critique was followed by two others: The Critique of Practical Reason and the Critique of judgment. The three books cover the true, good and beautiful respectively. By the word “critique” Kant meant a delineation of the fundamental or transcendent conditions necessary to any particular mental process.
                             In the work Critique of Pure Reason, Kant says all human have the ability to understand what happens around them. The data given by the outside world can be able to process, organize and comprehend by each individual. In the work Critique of Practical Reason attempts to provide a universal foundation for morals, the non-physical ideas, not the material realities. The first two books created a gap between the physical or sensible and non-physical or supersensible worlds. Humans have the freedom to think and make judgment, at the same time they are physical creatures subject to causalities. The third book Critique of Judgment narrowed the gap between sensible and supersensible.
The literature on the Critique of Judgment divides into two traditions, one focusing Kant’s overall philosophical project and the other focusing on the theory of art one can be derive from Kant’s work. Most of Kant’s example comes from nature, even though the book is about art. Aesthetic according to Kant experienced through senses than to something specifically artistic. The word “aesthetic” its Greek root means ‘of the senses’ aids Kant’s efforts to get from the sensory to the supersensible.

Critique of Judgment
The Critique of the Power of Judgment comprises of two main parts, the “Critique of Aesthetic Power of Judgment” and “Critique of the Teleological Power of Judgment”. The first of these discusses our judgments about beauty and sublimity in both nature and art that is called as aesthetic judgment. The second part discusses our judgments about the systematic organization of specific things within nature, namely organisms, as well as our tendency to think of nature as a whole as if it were a single as well as designed system and to that extent like one big organism itself.
                   Aesthetic judgments about the beautiful and sublime and teleological judgments about the goals of natural systems and of nature as a whole are both instances of what he calls “reflecting judgment” a use of judgment that seeks to discover a concept for a particular object that is given to it rather than to find particular object to which apply a concept that it already has.
                             Kant argues that both aesthetic and teleological judgments are strictly speaking non-cognitive: they may discover concepts or something like concepts and use them for various purposes, but they do not themselves yield knowledge.
                   A second connection between aesthetic and teleological judgment is both involve perceptions of what Kant called “Purposiveness” or goal directedness:  in finding an object beautiful or sublime, our experience of the object is purposive or satisfies a goal of our own even though we do not think of the object itself as having been designed for a purpose. Kant calls this “purposiveness without a purpose”. In teleological judgment we think of an organism or even the whole nature as if it were designed for a purpose, a conception of nature which is supposed to have heuristic value for us even though we do not and cannot know that anything in nature has been designed for a purpose.
                   According to Kant, what is subjective in a presentation of an object is its aesthetic character. The objective elements of a presentation are its logical validity. In order to understand an object, the two senses subjective and objective should be together. The subjective of a presentation is the reaction f pleasure and displeasure. Pleasure and displeasure is not a cognitive understanding, cognition means the process by which knowledge and understanding is developed in the mind.
The Judgment of Taste is Aesthetic: Kant says if we wish to judge anything is beautiful, we do not analyze it with means of cognition but by means of imagination. The representation of an object wholly to the subject and what is more to its feeling that is pleasure and displeasure. Actually this pleasure and displeasure does not contribute to our knowledge. The determining ground for judgment of taste is subjective. Even the representation of an object is rational but is referred in a judgment simply to the subject and its feelings, then the judgment at an extent aesthetic.
Delight which determine judgment of taste is our interest. The interest of a person is influenced by desire. For example, the judgment on the beautiful which is not interested or with least interest will be vary partial and not a pure judgment of taste. The disinterest in the representation will create pure moral judgment. So our liking largely influences our judgment.
In the critique, Kant next deals with ‘agreeable’ ‘good’ and ‘beautiful’ respectively. Kant gives definition to each idea. Let us start with agreeable. Agreeable is what the senses like in sensation. Agreeable is not simply what we like, but what please us. In order to find what is agreeable, there is no need of judgment at all about the character of the object that is made to enjoy- no need of all other judging. Next is good, we call something is good for if we like it only as a means. If it is useful to us we call it good. But we call something intrinsically good- or good in itself, if we like it for its own sake. The “good” always contains a concept of purpose.
                   Sometimes people misinterpret the terms ‘good’ and ‘agreeable’ as synonyms. But these are two different ideas. For judging goodness of an object a person should know the concept of it. But for gratification the determination of an object is not necessary. It is true that in many cases it seems as if the agreeable and the good are one and the same. People say all gratification, if it lasts, is intrinsically good. If we say an object is agreeable, we only attribute it to the senses. But if we call the object good, we bring it under the principle of reason and concept of purpose.
In simple words we can say that, Agreeable is what gratifies us, Beautiful is what we just like and good is what we esteem. Agreeable can be applicable to non-rational animals too. Beauty is only for human beings and the good holds for every rational being. Agreeable is a personal judgment because it differs from person to person. But it is quite different for “beautiful” if a person proclaims something beautiful then he/she requires same liking from others.
Judgment of agreeable is the taste of sense. Judgment of beautiful is the taste of reflection. But both judgments are aesthetic. Kant says a judgment of taste must involve a claim to subjective universality. Subjective universality means a person should judge the object as one containing ground of delight for all human beings.
                   A pure judgment of taste is independent of charm and emotion. The beauty is judge on the basis of its purposiveness not on the interest of reason, whether it gratifies or pains us. The judgment of taste made out of the charm and emotion lacks universality or in case if it gets wide acceptance, it is only because that judgment of taste diminished to the extent that sensations of that kind are included among the bases determining taste. It is a flaw that beauty is judged on the basis of material embellishments.
          According to Kant, there are two types of aesthetic judgments. The primary one is, Empirical judgments it asserts that an object or a way of presenting an object is agreeable or disagreeable. The second type is pure judgments, if it asserts that it is beautiful. Empirical aesthetic judgments are judgments of sense. Pure aesthetic judgments are properly judgment of taste.
There are two types of beauty, Free beauty and Accessory beauty. Free beauty does not presuppose a concept of what the object meant to be. Accessory beauty does presuppose and also object’s perfection in terms of that concept. The free kinds of beauty are called self-subsistent beauties of a thing. The accessory beauty is also called conditioned beauty, which judges a thing under the concept of a particular purpose. When we judge free beauty then our judgment of taste is pure.
 Kant’s concept of ideal of beauty says that there is no rule for taste that determines by concepts of what is beautiful. The universal concept of judging a beauty is empirical criterion. The subject’s feeling decides the beauty not the concept of an object. Ideal of imagination rests on exhibition not on concepts.
Kant also states that taste is a kind of sensus communis, a sense shared by all of us. The principle of this “common sense” is to think for oneself, in an unbiased way; to think from the perspective of everyone else. The base for judgment of taste is always subjective, but it assumes that the judgment is necessary for everyone, so it could be like an objective principle, demand universal acceptance.
                   In a judgment of taste the imagination must be considered in its freedom. Imagination is free and yet lawful of itself, the understanding alone gives the law. If a product judged in terms of a determinate law, it is not the judgment of taste.
The judgment of sublime: the beautiful and the sublime are similar in some respects. They both concerned with pleasure rather than knowledge. The pleasure arises from the way in which the object is presented to us, not the object itself. But there are some differences in beautiful and sublime. The beautiful is concerned about the form of the object, which consists in objects and bounded together, but sublime can also be found in formless object. Beautiful is the exhibition of an indeterminate concept of understanding. Sublime is the exhibition of an indeterminate concept of reason. In the case of beautiful our liking is connected with the presentation of quality, but in the case of sublime with the presentation of quantity. In sublimity not only positive pleasure as rather admiration and respect, and so should be called a negative pleasure. Sublime gives rise to a different response. Sublimity is the result of attunement, which means mental sensation that attends perceiving an object that exceeds the capacity of our senses. So the sublime is not in fact a quality of nature but our own minds.
Kant’s opinion on “nature as a might”: might is an ability that is superior to great obstacles. When in an aesthetic judgment we consider nature as a mighty that has no dominance over us, ten it is dynamically sublime; consider it as an object of fear. We consider an object fearful without being afraid of it. Thus a virtuous person fears God without being afraid of him. The person does not think of wanting resist God and his commandments as a possibility that should worry him. If in judging nature aesthetically we call it sublime, we do so not because nature arouses fear, but because it calls forth our strength to regard as small the objects of our natural concerns like property, health and life.
Kant comments upon art in general; the result of art distinguished from that of nature, the first being a work, the second is an effect. Art is production through freedom based on reason.  Art as a human skill also distinguished from science and art can predict the desired effect. Art is distinguished from craft. Art is also called as free art, and craft is called mercenary art and craft is regarded as labour attracts us only through its effect, which is pay.
What is genius according to Kant- the mental powers whose combination in certain relations constitutes genius are imagination and understanding. Kant says genius is a talent for art not for science. Since it is an artistic talent, it presupposes a determinate concept of the product, namely its purpose. Artistic talent manifests in itself not so much in the fact, that the proposed purpose is achieved in exhibiting a determinate concept.
At the last section Kant discuss beauty as the symbol of morality. He compares judgment of taste and judgment of moral. Kant says beauty is the symbol of morally good. Beautiful we like directly not in its concept as we do in morality. Beautiful we like without any interest but for morally good there is necessarily an interest. In judging the beautiful we present the freedom of the will and will’s harmony with universal laws and reasons. We present the subjective principle for judging the beautiful as universal. Moral judgment is capable of having determinate constitutive principles.
Kant’s basic notion is that a sensory experience of pleasure can move from the subjective, that is pleasing me, to the objective that should please everyone. He is not somehow averse to using art and literature for moral purposes; he is simply concerned to establish that these spheres have certain autonomy and that, when they are connected with other spheres such as morality and practical usefulness, the nature of the connection clearly understood.
Kant’s philosophy and aesthetics influenced widely, especially in the field of Romantic thought and Romantic conception of literary imagination. His notions of artistic form, aesthetic freedom, genius and the non-utilitarian, non-moral character of art exerted, for example, profound impact on his contemporaries Goethe and Schiller. Kant’s philosophy had less literary because his entire example came from the nature. But his ideas are applicable to literary fields too. Kant contributed to Romantic and Modern period and his characterization of art became target of Post World War II theorists and philosophers. Kant’s ideas are complicated so literary examples on his ideas are difficult to find.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Primary Source:
·        Leitch, Vincent B. (Ed). The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. NewYork: Norton, 2001. 499-535.Web.

Secondary source
·         Abrams, M. H. A Glossary of Literary Terms. Wadsworth: Cengage, 2012. Print

·        Habib, M. A. R. Literary Criticism from Plato to the Present: AN INTRODUCTION. Singapore: Blckwell, 2011.Print

  
      Gayer, Paul. Kant. NewYork:Routledge, 2006. Print.


No comments:

Post a Comment