TERM PAPER PREPARED BY MUHAMEDSHEHIN TV
WHO’S WHO OF SAMUEL JOHNSON
As countless
anecdotes attest, Samuel johnson was cantankerous and dogmatic. He
inveighed
against the philosopher George Berkeley's (1685-1753) apparent denial of
the
reality of the external world by kicking a stone and declaring, "I refute
him thus."
And
he coined many mordant aphorisms, such as "The road to hell is paved with
good
intentions"
and "Patriotism is the last refuge of a scoundrel." Theatrical,
deliberately
provocative,
and beloved by many friends and admired by fellow writers; Johnson is
one
of the most influential critics in English literary history. 'The best part of
every
author,"
Johnson affirmed, "is in general to be found in his book," and this
is trite in
his
own case. Though he often chastised himself for indolence, fearful that
salvation
would
be denied to him because he was not fully using his great gifts, he was in fact
astonishingly
productive, and in many genres. His literary labors include a monumental
Dictionary
of the English Language, a comprehensive edition of Shakespeare,
and
the Lives of the English Poets, a set of insightful, vividly written
biographical arid
literary
portraits of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century authors.
Johnson
was born at Lichfield, Staffordshire, a town about 100 miles northwest
of
London. His father was a bookseller, and his education consisted largely of the
volumes
in his father’s bookshop and
what was "whipped" into him by the master
of
the grammar school in Lichfield. He attended Pembroke College at Oxford for
only
a year, leaving in December 1729 because he lacked the funds to continue. At
Oxford,
he later recounted, "I was miserably
poor,
and 1 thought to fight my way by
my
literature and my wit"; the fight, continuing in later years, would leave
him in
poverty
for most of his life.
Johnson
was an intense, discerning reader; as the economist Adam Smith recalled,
"Johnson
knew more books than any man 'alive." While at oxford, he pored over the
popular
devotional tract A Serious Call to a Devout lend Holy Lifo (1729),
by the
schoolmaster
and minister William Law. He termed Law's book "the ·finest piece of
hortatory
theology in any language," and it is the foundation for the prayers and
meditations
that he composed later in his life.
SAMUEL JOHNSON PREFACE TO SHAKESPEARE
(1765)
In
his preface to his edition of the collected works of Shakespeare, Johnson
begins by noting that we often seem to cherish the works of the past and to
neglect the present. Praises, he writes, are often “without reason lavished on
the dead” (320) as a result of which it sometimes seems that the “honours due
only to excellence are paid to antiquity” (320). Everyone, Johnson suggests, is
“perhaps . . . more willing to honour past than present excellence; and the
mind contemplates genius through the shades of age” (320). Time is the test of
genius, Johnson contends:
To
works . . . of which the excellence is not absolute and definite, but gradual
and
comparative;
to works not raised upon principles demonstrative and scientific, but
appealing
wholly to observation and experience, no other test can be applied than length
of
duration and continuance of esteem. What mankind have long possessed they have
often
examined and compared; and if they persist to value the possession, it is
because
frequent
comparisons have confirmed opinion in its favour. . . . [I]n the productions of
genius,
nothing can be styled excellent till it has been compared with other works of
the
same
kind. (320)
With
this test in mind, Johnson suggests that Shakespeare meets these criteria and
“may now begin to assume the dignity of an ancient, and earn the privilege of
established fame and prescriptive veneration” (321) because he has “long
outlived his century, the term commonly used as the test of literary
merit”(321). That he deserves such acclaim can be verified by “comparing him
with other authors” (321). The question which arises, given the fallibility of
“human judgment” (321), is “by what peculiarities of excellence Shakespeare has
gained and kept the favour of his countrymen?” (321). Johnson argues that
Shakespeare’s perhaps most important skill concerns accurate characterisation:
he offers “representations of general nature” (321) rather than of “particular
manners” (321) peculiar to individuals or particular places and times. In a
view of Shakespeare that has come to be constantly regurgitated, he praises the
Bard’s characterisation in particular for its fidelity to human nature in
general:
Shakespeare
is above all writers . . . the poet of nature; the poet that holds up to his
readers
a faithful mirror of manners and of life. His characters are not modified by
the
customs
of particular places, unpractised by the rest of the world; by the
peculiarities of
studies
and professions . . .; or by the accidents of transient fashions or temporary
opinions:
they are the genuine progeny of common humanity, such as the world will
always
supply, and observation will always find. His persons act and speak by the
influence
of those general passions and principles by which all minds are agitated. . . .
In
the writings of other poets a character is too often an individual; in those of
Shakespeare
it is commonly a species. (321).Where other dramatists offer “hyperbolic or
aggravated characters” (322), Shakespeare’s “scenes are occupied only be men,
who act and speak as the reader thinks that he should himself have spoken or acted
on the same occasion” (322). Characterisation “ample and general” (322) in this
way, that is, his “adherence to general nature” (322), is supplemented by
appropriate strokes of individuality: “no poet ever kept his personages more distinct
from each other. . . . [T]hough some may be equally adapted to every person, it
will be difficult to find any that can be properly transferred from the present
possessor to another claimant” (322).
However,
Johnson hastens to add, Shakespeare “always makes nature predominate over accident;
and if he preserves the essential character, is not very carefully of
distinctions superinduced and adventitious”(322).Even when dealing with
supernatural matters, Johnson stresses, Shakespeare “approximates the remote,
and familiarises the wonderful; the event which he represents will not happen,
but if it were possible, its effects would probably be such as he has assigned”
(322). All in all, Shakespeare “has not only shewn human nature as it acts in
real exigencies, but as it would be found in trials, to which it cannot be exposed”(322).
Whatever his subject matter, as Shakespeare’s personages act upon principles
arising from genuine passion, very little modified by particular forms, their
pleasures and vexations are communicable to all times and to all places; they
are natural, and therefore durable; the adventitious peculiarities of personal habits,
are only superficial dies, bright and pleasing for a little while, yet soon
fading to a dim tinct, without any remains of former lustre; but the
discriminations fo true passion are the colours of nature; they pervade the
whole mass, and can only perish with the body that exhibits them. (323-324) As
such, his “drama is the mirror of life” (322) from which other writers can
learn much simply “by reading human sentiments in human language, by scenes
from which a hermit may estimate the transactions of the world, and a confessor
predict the progress of the passions” (322).
Moreover,
if his characterisation is realistic, so too are his dialogues. Johnson, the
editor of the first dictionary of the English language, argues that Shakespeare
has captured the enduring spirit of the English language: there is in every
nation, a style which never becomes obsolete, a certain mode of phraseology so consonant
and congenial to the analogy and principles of its respective language as to remain
settled and unaltered; this style is probably to be sought in the common intercourse
of life, among those who speak only to be understood, without ambition of elegance.
The polite are always catching modish innovations, and the learned depart from
established forms of speech, in hope of finding or making better; those who
wish for distinction forsake the vulgar. . . . [B]ut there is a conversation
above grossness and below refinement, where propriety resides, and where this
poet seems to have gathered his comic dialogue. (324) The speech of each of
Shakespeare’s characters is “so evidently determined by the incident which produces
it, and is pursued with so much ease and simplicity, that it seems scarcely to
claim the merit of fiction, but to have been gleaned by diligent selection out
of common conversation, and common occurrences” (321). Johnson then turns his
attention to the criticisms commonly made of Shakespeare’s plays, not least
that he did not follow the prescribed rules. Firstly, he deals with the view
that Shakespeare is guilty of blurring the genres of tragedy and comedy which
ought to be distinct. Johnson argues that the ancient poets, out of the “chaos of
mingled purposes and casualties” (322) and “according to the laws which custom
had prescribed” (322), had “selected, some the crimes of men, and some their
absurdities; some the momentous vicissitudes of life, and some the lighter
occurrences; some th terrors of distress and some the gaieties of prosperity”
(322). It was for this reason that there “rose two modes of imitation, known by
the names of tragedy and comedy, compositions intended to promote different
ends by contrary means, and considered . . . little allied” (322). More
recently, Johnson contends, there has been a tendency to divide Shakespeare’s
work into tragedies, comedies and histories but that these are not distinguished
“by any very exact or definite ideas” (323). For these, comedy was defined
simply as an “action which ended happily to the principal persons, however
serious or distressful through its intermediate incidents” (323). To be a
tragedy, similarly, “required only a calamitous conclusion” (323), as a result
of which “plays were written, which, by changing the catastrophe, were
tragedies today, and comedies tomorrow” (323). Histories were viewed as plays
consisting of a “series of actions, with no other than chronological
succession, independent on each other” (323). Histories, Johnson argues, are
“not
always very nicely distinguished from tragedy” (323). Johnson argues that Shakespeare’s
plays, however, through “all these denominations of the drama” (323), are
neither tragedies nor comedies in the strict sense of these terms, but compositions
of a distinct kind; exhibiting the real state of sublunary nature which partakes
of good and evil, joy and sorrow, mingled with endless variety of proportion
and innumerable modes of combination; and expressing the course of the world,
in which the loss of the one is the gain of the other. (322) Shakespeare has
“united the powers of exciting laughter and sorrow not only in one mind, but in
one composition” (323) as a result of which almost all his plays are “divided
between serious and ludicrous characters” (323). Shakespeare’s “mode of
composition” (323) is always the same: an “interchange of seriousness and
merriment, by which the mind is softened at one time, and exhilarated at
another” (323). Johnson justifies Shakespeare’s “mingled drama” (323) on the
grounds that the mixture of sorrow and joy is more realistic and, thus, morally
instructive:
there
is always an appeal open from criticism to nature; . . . the end of poetry is
to
instruct
by pleasing. That the mingled drama may convey all the instruction of tragedy
or
comedy cannot be denied, because it includes both in its alteration of
exhibition and
approaches
nearer than either to the appearance of life. (323)
In response to the “specious” (323) view that
the “change of scenes” (323) in this way causes the “passions” (323) to be
“interrupted in their progression” (323) and “wants at last the power to move” (323),
Johnson argues that the”interchanges of mingled scenes seldom fail to produce
the intended vicissitudes of passion. Fiction cannot move so much, but that the
attention may be easily transferred”(323). All “pleasure persists in variety”
(323).Johnson then proceeds to list all the defects which many have detected in
Shakespeare’s plays.The most important of these is his failure to respect the
unities of action, time and place. Johnson is on Shakespeare’s side in these
respects. With regard to the unity of action, Johnson argues that the laws applicable
to tragedies and comedies are not applicable to Shakespeare’s histories. All
that is required of such plays is that the “changes of action be so prepared as
to be understood, that the incidents be various and affecting, and the
characters consistent, natural, and distinct. No other unity is intended, and therefore
none is sought” (325). In the other plays, there is unity of action: “his plan
has commonly what Aristotle requires, a beginning, a middle and an end; one
event is concatenated with another, and the conclusion follows by easy
consequence” (325). The “end of the play is the end of expectation” (325). With
regard to the unities of time and place, Johnson argues that these “are not
essential to a just drama” (327) even though they arise from the “supposed
necessity of making the drama credible” (325). The argument is that the “mind revolts
from evident falsehood, and fiction loses its force when it departs from the
resemblance of reality” (326) as a result of which the failure to depict on
stage one location and a duration corresponding to the length of the audience’s
presence in the auditorium is dramatic heresy. All this does not matter,
Johnson argues, because “spectators are always in their senses and know . . . that
the stage is only a stage” (326). Vraisemblance is not adversely affected,
firstly, by changes in location: the “different actions that complete a story
may be in places very remote from each other; and where is the absurdity of
allowing that space to represent first Athen, and then Sicily, which was always
known to be neither Sicily nor Athens, but a modern theatre?” (326), he asks.
Secondly, he argues, time is “obsequious to the imagination; a lapse of years
is as easily conceived as a passage of hours. Incontemplation we easily
contract the time of real actions, and therefore willingly permit it to be
contracted when we only see their imitation” (326). All in all, the “delight of
tragedy proceeds from the consciousness of fiction; if we thought
murders and treasons real, they would please no more” . “Imitations produce
pain or pleasure, not because they are mistaken for realities, but because they
bring realities to mind” (326).
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Norton
anthology of criticism and theory
Abrams,
M.H. A Glossary of Literary Terms. Wadsworth: Cengage,
Nagarajan,
M.S. English Literary Criticism and Theory; An Introduction.
No comments:
Post a Comment