TERM PAPER
CRITICAL TRANSACTION : ARISTOTLE
TO ELIOT
Walter Pater: From Studies in the History of
the Renaissance
Remi Mohandas
I MA ECL
LCL051517
Walter Pater was
born on August 4th 1839, Shadwell, London .He was a critic essayist
and humanist whose advocacy of art for art sake became a cardinal doctrine of
the movement know as aesthesis . Pater was educated at king’s school Canterbury
and at queens college oxford where studied philosophy under Benjamine Jowelt .
Pater early intention to enter the church gave way the interest in classical
studies. The essay like Leonard da vince , Pico della Mirandola and other essay
were collected in 1837 as studies in the history of renaissance. This delicate
and sensitive appreciation of Renaissances are is these essay is made
reputation as a scholar and an aesthetic and he became the centre
of a small group of admirers in Oxford . In the concluding essay the
Renaissances Pater asserted that art exist for the sake of its beauty alone,
and that it acknowledge neither moral standers nor utilitarian function in its
reason for being. He dedicated Studies in the History of Renaissances to his
close friend C L Shadwell. Peters first essay was published anonymously in the
later 1860s..
Marius the Epicurean
(1885) is his most substantial work. It is a philosophical romance in which
Pater’s ideal of an aesthetic and religious life is scrupulously and
elaborately set forth. The setting is Rome in the time of Marcus Aurelius; but
this is a thin disguise for the characteristically late-19th-century spiritual
development of its main character. Imaginary Portraits (1887) are
shorter pieces of philosophical fiction in the same mode. Appreciations
(1889) is a return to the critical
essay, this time largely on English subjects. In 1893 came Plato and
Platonism, giving an extremely literary view of Plato and neglecting the
logical and dialectical side of his philosophy. Pater’s Greek Studies
(1895), Miscellaneous Studies (1895), and Essays from The Guardian
(privately printed, 1896; 1901) were published posthumously; also published
posthumously was his unfinished romance, Gaston de Latour (1896).
The
primary influence on Pater’s mind was his classical studies, colored by a
highly individual view of Christian devotion and pursued largely as a source of
extremely refined artistic sensations. In his later critical writings Pater
continued to focus on the innate qualities of works of art, in contrast to the
prevailing tendency to evaluate them on the basis of their moral and
educational value.
Pater’s
early influence was confined to a small circle in Oxford, but he came to have a
widespread effect on the next literary generation. Oscar Wilde, George Moore, and the
aesthetes of the 1890s were among his followers and show obvious and continual
traces both of his style and of his ideas.
Pater's
first essays were published anonymously in the late 1 860s. A study of
Coleridge in the Westminster Review (1866) suggests that Pater found a
central theme ·early on: "Modern thought is distinguished from ancient by
its cultivation of the 'relative' spirit in place of the 'absolute.' ... To the
modern spirit nothing is, or can be rightly known, except relatively and under
certain conditions."
Studies
in the History of the Renaissance, a collection of essays on writers and Italian painter appeared four
years later.
Pater's
next book, the romance Manus the Epicurean (1885), describes the
development of a young Roman in the time of Marcus Aurelius, the second-century
C.E. Roman emperor and Stoic philosopher. He conceived it as the first of a three-part
series-the second to be set in. sixteenth -century France and' the third in late eighteenth-century
England-but the other volume!! remained unwritten
Studies
in the History of the Renaissance was a momentous text for a number of Pater's younger contemporaries,
including Oscar Wilde. Pater states that his primary concern is with Italy in
the fifteenth century, but he deliberately defines the term Renaissance much
more widely, describing it as an "outbreak of the human spirit" from
the "limits which the religious system of the middle ages imposed on the
heart and the imagination."
Throughout
the book, Pater emphasizes the precious, fine textures of art, but always with
the implication that only persons of rich receptiveness, of exquisite and
accurate perception, can wholly sense and appreciate its singularities. Many
attacks for advocating pleasure as the heights good and self gratification as the best rule for the conduct of life and
some of the critic accuse Pater for projecting 19th century thinking
into the Renaissances. To defend himself from all these charges Pater charge
the title of the second edition to the Renaissance
: Studies in Art and Poetry and omitted the conclusion which declared that
nothing matters more than the experience of brilliant moments.
In the
preface he tells the critic should seek general definition for key terms. He
declared that beauty like all other qualities presented to human experience is
relative. Pater intimates that there is no difference between life and art ,
nature and culture each matters only in so far as it gives pleasure.
Pater at first seems to directly challenge Arnold's dictum that the critic must see the object as in itself it really is by adding a necessary first step is "to know one's own impression as it really is, to discriminate it, to realize it ." the goal is the same that is knowing the impression is the means through, Which is one how and why one is. And one is deeply moved by the presence of beautiful objects." This response to art matters because according to Pater, it is frees in each form being a solitary prisoner in its own dream. of a world, the most important is the free individual from their bondage. Pater registers a heightened sense of fleeting beauty wherever it materializes, the qualities is also evident in so-called decadent literature and impressionist painting of the time. Pater's view of criticism and art startled his contemporaries, because God is absent from the life. Most of them saw death not as a final but as the pathway to the highest form
Pater at first seems to directly challenge Arnold's dictum that the critic must see the object as in itself it really is by adding a necessary first step is "to know one's own impression as it really is, to discriminate it, to realize it ." the goal is the same that is knowing the impression is the means through, Which is one how and why one is. And one is deeply moved by the presence of beautiful objects." This response to art matters because according to Pater, it is frees in each form being a solitary prisoner in its own dream. of a world, the most important is the free individual from their bondage. Pater registers a heightened sense of fleeting beauty wherever it materializes, the qualities is also evident in so-called decadent literature and impressionist painting of the time. Pater's view of criticism and art startled his contemporaries, because God is absent from the life. Most of them saw death not as a final but as the pathway to the highest form
of
life. Pater neither offers any religious consolation nor invokes the moral
seriousness
of the
earlier Victorian writers, including Thomas Carlyle, Arnold, and Eliot. This is the main limitation of his
position, the responsibility of the critic is to maximizing his or her pleasure, not contributing to
knowledge or to change in a body politic.
From Studies in the History of the
Renaissance
In the
preface to his The Renaissance: Studies in Art and Poetry, Pater rejects
as useless any attempt to define “beauty in the abstract.” While on the surface
Pater claims to accept Matthew Arnold’s imperative that the function of true
criticism is to “see the object as in itself it really is,” he redefines this
formula in a subjective way: to see the object as it really is, he says, “is to
know one’s own impression as it really is, to discriminate it, to realize it
distinctly” . The kinds of questions we should ask are: “What is this
song or picture . . . to me? What effect does it really produce on me?” The
answers to these questions are the “original facts” which must be confronted by
the critic.
Pater’s
views of aesthetic experience are rooted in his account of experience in general.
In the conclusion to Studies he observes that modern thought tends to
view all things as in constant flux. Our physical life is a “perpetual motion”
of ever changing combinations of elements and forces. This is even more true of
our mental life, of the world of thought and feeling. At first sight, he says,
“experience seems to bury us under a flood of external objects . . . But when
reflexion begins to play on those objects they are dissipated under its
influence . . . the whole scope of observation is dwarfed into the narrow
chamber of the individual mind”. Hence the world which seemed
overwhelming, which seemed solid and external and of boundless scope, is
actually encompassed within the circle of our impressions, our experience . Not only does the whole world reduce itself to our impressions, but
these impressions themselves are ever vanishing and in “perpetual flight” . Given the brevity of our life, we must “be for ever curiously testing
new opinions and courting new impressions, never acquiescing in a facile
orthodoxy, of Comte, or of Hegel, or of our own.” For Pater, experience must be
undertaken for its own sake: “Not the fruit of experience, but experience
itself, is the end To burn always with
this hard, gem-like flame, to maintain this ecstasy, is success in life” Such
intense experience is furnished foremost by “the poetic passion, the desire of
beauty, the love of art for its own sake” Pater visited Italy in 1865 and was deeply
affected by the Renaissance paintings he saw in Florence and elsewhere. The
subject themselves are the French, Italian and German writes , painters ranging
from the 15th to the 18th century in whom lives and in
whose work Pater finds represented in many sides the divergent attitude of the
Renaissances.
The
task of the aesthetic critic he says is first to realize distinctly the exact
impression that a work of art makes upon him or her , then to determine
the source and condition ‘the virtue’ of
that impression and finally to express that virtue so that the impression it
has made on him may be shared by others. The Renaissance is the record of the impression
induced in the refined sensibility of Pater by the art of the studies. Wordsworth's poetry and then the function of
the critic of Wordsworth is to follow up that active principle ,to disengage
it, to mark the degree in which it penetrates his verse
We have
here reached a point in Western culture where experience is disrupted and
abstracted from any kind of constraint whatsoever, even from its consensual
overlap with that of other individuals. Hegel would have regarded such
experience as an abstract category, not even possible; but Pater expresses a
desperate attempt to redeem experience from the weight of centuries of
oppression and coercion and molding into various socially acceptable forms. He
effectively aestheticisms experience, equating the fullness of experience with
beauty, in an attempt to extricate the category of experience from the burdens
invested in it by bourgeois thought. Experience is no longer a reliable source
of knowledge or a basis of scientific inquiry; it is not a realm which
constrains the operations of reason; nor is it a realm under the strict
surveillance of morality or of religious institutions. It is raised from the
mereness of means to the exaltation offend, a celebration of purposelessness, a
celebration of indirection,
The most influential pages of the Renaissances
come in a brief conclusion of the aesthetic manifesto adapted from the Pater
1868 review of William Morris .Earthly paradise turns away from the explicit
subject of Renaissance art to address the reader directly. What matter
according to Pater is not any of the usual Victorian middle class values of
Christian faith or social status nor any kind of public life. The Renaissance
as a unified historical period ended with the fall of Rome in 1527. The strains
between Christian faith and classical humanism led to Mannerism
in the latter part of the 16th century. Great works of art animated by the
Renaissance spirit, however, continued to be made in northern Italy and in
northern Europe. One important part of that later Renaissance, according
to Pater, was the effort made by fifteenth century Italian scholars “to
reconcile Christianity with the religion of ancient Greece.” Giovanni Pico
della Mirandola typified that effort, in his writings as well as his life; he
was “reconciled indeed to the new religion, but still [had] a tenderness for
the earlier life.” Lacking the historic sense, Pico and his contemporaries
sought in vain, as Pater saw it, a reconciliation based on allegorical
interpretations of religious belief: The “Renaissance of the fifteenth century
was . . . great, rather by what it designed . . . than by what it actually
achieved.”
Pater wants his readers to take
pleasure in sense impression and the pursuit of knowledge , whether admiring an
artwork or another person.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
William E.
Buckler, Walter Pater: The Cd.tic as Artist of Ideas (1987)
Jonathan
Loesberg, Aesthetic and
Deconstruction
Nagarajan , M S. English Literary Criticism and Theory.
Hyderabad . Orient BlackSwan Private Limited , 2006
No comments:
Post a Comment